Skip to main content
Advertisement
  • Loading metrics

Evolutionary Establishment of Moral and Double Moral Standards through Spatial Interactions

  • Dirk Helbing ,

    dhelbing@ethz.ch

    Affiliations ETH Zurich, Zurich, Switzerland, Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, New Mexico, United States of America, Collegium Budapest - Institute for Advanced Study, Budapest, Hungary

  • Attila Szolnoki,

    Affiliation Research Institute for Technical Physics and Materials Science, Budapest, Hungary

  • Matjaž Perc,

    Affiliation Faculty of Natural Sciences and Mathematics, University of Maribor, Maribor, Slovenia

  • György Szabó

    Affiliation Research Institute for Technical Physics and Materials Science, Budapest, Hungary

Abstract

Situations where individuals have to contribute to joint efforts or share scarce resources are ubiquitous. Yet, without proper mechanisms to ensure cooperation, the evolutionary pressure to maximize individual success tends to create a tragedy of the commons (such as over-fishing or the destruction of our environment). This contribution addresses a number of related puzzles of human behavior with an evolutionary game theoretical approach as it has been successfully used to explain the behavior of other biological species many times, from bacteria to vertebrates. Our agent-based model distinguishes individuals applying four different behavioral strategies: non-cooperative individuals (“defectors”), cooperative individuals abstaining from punishment efforts (called “cooperators” or “second-order free-riders”), cooperators who punish non-cooperative behavior (“moralists”), and defectors, who punish other defectors despite being non-cooperative themselves (“immoralists”). By considering spatial interactions with neighboring individuals, our model reveals several interesting effects: First, moralists can fully eliminate cooperators. This spreading of punishing behavior requires a segregation of behavioral strategies and solves the “second-order free-rider problem”. Second, the system behavior changes its character significantly even after very long times (“who laughs last laughs best effect”). Third, the presence of a number of defectors can largely accelerate the victory of moralists over non-punishing cooperators. Fourth, in order to succeed, moralists may profit from immoralists in a way that appears like an “unholy collaboration”. Our findings suggest that the consideration of punishment strategies allows one to understand the establishment and spreading of “moral behavior” by means of game-theoretical concepts. This demonstrates that quantitative biological modeling approaches are powerful even in domains that have been addressed with non-mathematical concepts so far. The complex dynamics of certain social behaviors become understandable as the result of an evolutionary competition between different behavioral strategies.

Author Summary

Why do friends spontaneously come up with mutually accepted rules, cooperation, and solidarity, while the creation of shared moral standards often fails in large communities? In a “global village”, where everybody may interact with anybody else, it is not worthwhile to punish people who cheat. Moralists (cooperative individuals who undertake punishment efforts) disappear because of their disadvantage compared to cooperators who do not punish (so-called “second-order free-riders”). However, cooperators are exploited by free-riders. This creates a “tragedy of the commons”, where everybody is uncooperative in the end. Yet, when people interact with friends or local neighbors, as most people do, moralists can escape the direct competition with non-punishing cooperators by separating from them. Moreover, in the competition with free-riders, moralists can defend their interests better than non-punishing cooperators. Therefore, while seriously depleted in the beginning, moralists can finally spread all over the world (“who laughs last laughs best effect”). Strikingly, the presence of a few non-cooperative individuals (“deviant behavior”) can accelerate the victory of moralists. In order to spread, moralists may also form an “unholy cooperation” with people having double moral standards, i.e., free-riders who punish non-cooperative behavior, while being uncooperative themselves.

Introduction

Public goods such as environmental resources or social benefits are particularly prone to exploitation by non-cooperative individuals (“defectors”), who try to increase their benefit at the expense of fair contributors or users, the “cooperators”. This implies a tragedy of commons [1]. It was proposed that costly punishment of non-cooperative individuals can establish cooperation in public goods dilemmas [2][8], and it is effective indeed [9][11]. Nonetheless, why would cooperators choose to punish defectors at a personal cost [12][14]? One would expect that evolutionary pressure should eventually eliminate such “moralists” due to their extra costs compared to “second-order free-riders” (i.e. cooperators, who do not punish). These, however should finally be defeated by “free-riders” (defectors). To overcome this problem [15], [16], it was proposed that cooperators who punish defectors (called “moralists” by us) would survive through indirect reciprocity [17], reputation effects [18] or the possibility to abstain from the joint enterprize [19][21] by “volunteering” [22], [23]. Without such mechanisms, cooperators who punish will usually vanish. Surprisingly, however, the second-order free-rider problem is naturally resolved, without assuming additional mechanisms, if spatial or network interactions are considered. This will be shown in the following.

In order to study the conditions for the disappearance of non-punishing cooperators and defectors, we simulate the public goods game with costly punishment, considering two cooperative strategies (C, M) and two defective ones (D, I). For illustration, one may imagine that cooperators (C) correspond to countries trying to meet the CO emission standards of the Kyoto protocol [24], and “moralists” (M) to cooperative countries that additionally enforce the standards by international pressure (e.g. embargoes). Defectors (D) would correspond to those countries ignoring the Kyoto protocol, and immoralists (I) to countries failing to meet the Kyoto standards, but nevertheless imposing pressure on other countries to fulfil them. According to the classical game-theoretical prediction, all countries would finally fail to meet the emission standards, but we will show that, in a spatial setting, interactions between the four strategies C, D, M, and I can promote the spreading of moralists. Other well-known public goods problems are over-fishing, the pollution of our environment, the creation of social benefit systems, or the establishment and maintenance of cultural institutions (such as a shared language, norms, values, etc.).

Our simplified game-theoretical description of such problems assumes that cooperators (C) and moralists (M) make a contribution of to the respective public good under consideration, while nothing is contributed by defectors (D) and “immoralists” (I), i.e. defectors who punish other defectors. The sum of all contributions is multiplied by a factor reflecting synergy effects of cooperation, and the resulting amount is equally shared among the interacting individuals. Moreover, moralists and immoralists impose a fine on each defecting individual (playing D or I), which produces an additional cost per punished defector to them (see Methods for details). The division by scales for the group size, but for simplicity, the parameter is called the punishment fine and the punishment cost.

Given the same interaction partners, an immoralist never gets a higher payoff than a defector, but does equally well in a cooperative environment. Moreover, a cooperator tends to outperform a moralist, given the interaction partners are the same. However, a cooperator can do better than a defector when the punishment fine is large enough.

It is known that punishment in the public goods game and similar games can promote cooperation above a certain critical threshold of the synergy factor [11], [25]. Besides cooperators who punish defectors, Heckathorn considered “full cooperators” (moralists) and “hypocritical cooperators” (immoralists) [26]. For well-mixed interactions (where individuals interact with a representative rather than local strategy distribution), Eldakar and Wilson find that altruistic punishment (moralists) can spread, if second-order free-riders (non-punishing altruists) are excluded, and that selfish punishers (immoralists) can survive together with altruistic non-punishers (cooperators), provided that selfish nonpunishers (defectors) are sufficiently scarce [27].

Besides well-mixed interactions, some researchers have also investigated the effect of spatial interactions [5], [11], [28], [29], since it is known that they can support the survival or spreading of cooperators [30] (but this is not always the case [31], [32]). In this way, Brandt et al. discovered a coexistence of cooperators and defectors for certain parameter combinations [11]. Compared to these studies, our model assumes somewhat different replication and strategy updating rules. The main point, however, is that we have chosen long simulation times and scanned the parameter space more extensively, which revealed several new insights, for example, the possible coexistence of immoralists and moralists, even when a substantial number of defectors is present initially. When interpreting our results within the context of moral dynamics [33], our main discoveries for a society facing public goods games may be summarized as follows:

  1. Victory over second-order free-riders: Over a long enough time period, moralists fully eliminate cooperators, thereby solving the “second-order free-rider problem”. This becomes possible by spatial segregation of the two cooperative strategies C and M, where the presence of defectors puts moralists in a advantageous position, which eventually allows moralists to get rid of non-punishing cooperators.
  2. “Who laughs last laughs best effect”: Moralists defeat cooperators even when the defective strategies I and D are eventually eliminated, but this process is very slow. That is, the system behavior changes its character significantly even after very long times. This is the essence of the “who laughs last laughs best effect”. The finally winning strategy can be in a miserable situation in the beginning, and its victory may take very long.
  3. “Lucifer's positive side effect”: By permanently generating a number of defectors, small mutation rates can considerably accelerate the spreading of moralists.
  4. “Unholy collaboration” of moralists with immoralists: Under certain conditions, moralists can survive by profiting from immoralists. This actually provides the first explanation for the existence of defectors, who hypocritically punish other defectors, although they defect themselves. The occurrence of this strange behavior is well-known in reality and even experimentally confirmed [34], [35].

These discoveries required a combination of theoretical considerations and extensive computer simulations on multiple processors over long time horizons.

Results

For well-mixed interactions, defectors are the winners of the evolutionary competition among the four behavioral strategies C, D, M, and I [36], which implies a tragedy of the commons despite punishment efforts. The reason is that cooperators (second-order free-riders) spread at the cost of moralists, while requiring them for their own survival.

Conclusions from computer simulations are strikingly different, if the assumption of well-mixed interactions is replaced by the more realistic assumption of spatial interactions. When cooperators and defectors interact in space [5], [11], [37][44], it is known that some cooperators can survive through spatial clustering [45]. However, it is not clear how the spatiotemporal dynamics and the frequency of cooperation would change in the presence of moralists and immoralists. Would spatial interactions be able to promote the spreading of punishment and thereby eliminate second-order free-riders?

In order to explore this, we have scanned a large parameter space. Figure 1 shows the resulting state of the system as a function of the punishment cost and punishment fine after a sufficiently long transient time. If the fine-to-cost ratio and the synergy factor are low, defectors eliminate all other strategies. However, for large enough fines , cooperators and defectors are always eliminated, and moralists prevail (Fig. 1).

thumbnail
Figure 1. Phase diagrams showing the remaining strategies in the spatial public goods game with cooperators (C), defectors (D), moralists (M) and immoralists (I), after a sufficiently long transient time.

Initially, each of the four strategies occupies 25% of the sites of the square lattice, and their distribution is uniform in space. However, due to their evolutionary competition, two or three strategies die out after some time. The finally resulting state depends on the synergy of cooperation, the punishment cost , and the punishment fine . The displayed phase diagrams are for (a) , (b) , and (d) . (d) Enlargement of the small-cost area for . Solid separating lines indicate that the resulting fractions of all strategies change continuously with a modification of the model parameters and , while broken lines correspond to discontinuous changes. All diagrams show that cooperators cannot stop the spreading of moralists, if only the fine-to-cost ratio is large enough. Furthermore, there are parameter regions where moralist can crowd out cooperators in the presence of defectors. Note that the spreading of moralists is extremely slow and follows a voter model kind of dynamics [46], if their competition with cooperators occurs in the absence of defectors. Therefore, computer simulations had to be run over extremely long times (up to iterations for a systems size of ). For similar reasons, a small level of strategy mutations (which permanently creates a small number of strategies of all kinds, in particular defectors) can largely accelerate the spreading of moralists in the M phase, while it does not significantly change the resulting fractions of the four strategies [51]. The existence of immoralists is usually not relevant for the outcome of the evolutionary dynamics. Apart from a very small parameter area, where immoralists and moralists coexist, immoralists are quickly extinct. Therefore, the 4-strategy model usually behaves like a model with the three strategies C, D, and M only. As a consequence, the phase diagrams for the latter look almost the same like the ones presented here [58].

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000758.g001

At larger values, when the punishment costs are moderate, we find a coexistence of moralists with defectors without any cooperators. To understand why moralists can outperform cooperators despite additional punishment costs, it is important to analyze the dynamics of spatial interactions. Starting with a homogeneous strategy distribution (Fig. 2a), the imitation of better-performing neighbors generates small clusters of individuals with identical strategies (Fig. 2b). “Immoralists” die out quickly, while cooperators and moralists form separate clusters in a sea of defectors (Fig. 2c). The further development is determined by the interactions at the interfaces between clusters of different strategies (Figs. 2d–f). In the presence of defectors, the fate of moralists is not decided by a direct competition with cooperators, but rather by the success of both cooperative strategies against invasion attempts by defectors. If the -ratio is appropriate, moralists respond better to defectors than cooperators. Indeed, moralists can spread so successfully in the presence of defectors that areas lost by cooperators are quickly occupied by moralists (supplementary Video S1). This indirect territorial battle ultimately leads to the extinction of cooperators (Fig. 2f), thus resolving the second-order free-rider problem.

thumbnail
Figure 2. Elimination of second-order free-riders (non-punishing cooperators) in the spatial public goods game with costly punishment for , , and .

(a) Initially, at time , cooperators (blue), defectors (red), moralists (green) and immoralists (yellow) are uniformly distributed over the spatial lattice. (b) After a short time period (here, at ), defectors prevail. (c) After 100 iterations, immoralists have almost disappeared, and cooperators prevail, since cooperators earn high payoffs when organized in clusters. (d) At , there is a segregation of moralists and cooperators, with defectors in between. (e) The evolutionary battle continues between cooperators and defectors on the one hand, and defectors and moralists on the other hand (here at ). (f) At , cooperators have been eliminated by defectors, and a small fraction of defectors survives among a large majority of moralists. Interestingly, each strategy (apart from I) has a time period during which it prevails, but only moralists can maintain their majority. While moralists perform poorly in the beginning, they are doing well in the end. We refer to this as the “who laughs last laughs best” effect.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000758.g002

In conclusion, the presence of some conventional free-riders (defectors) supports the elimination of second-order free-riders. However, if the fine-to-cost ratio is high, defectors are eliminated after some time. Then, the final struggle between moralists and cooperators takes such a long time that cooperators and moralists seem to coexist in a stable way. Nevertheless, a very slow coarsening of clusters is revealed, when simulating over extremely many iterations. This process is finally won by moralists, as they are in the majority by the time the defectors disappear, while they happen to be in the minority during the first stage of the simulation (see Fig. 2). We call this the “who laughs last laughs best effect”. Since the payoffs of cooperators and moralists are identical in the absence of other strategies, the underlying coarsening dynamics is expected to agree with the voter model [46].

Note that there is always a punishment fine , for which moralists can outcompete all other strategies. The higher the synergy factor , the lower the -ratio required to reach the prevalence of moralists. Yet, for larger values of , the system behavior also becomes richer, and there are areas for small fines or high punishment costs, where clusters with different strategies can coexist (see Figs. 1b–d). For example, we observe the coexistence of clusters of moralists and defectors (see Fig. 2 and supplementary Video S1) or of cooperators and defectors (see supplementary Video S2).

Finally, for low punishment costs but moderate punishment fines and synergy factors (see Fig. 1d), the survival of moralists may require the coexistence with “immoralists” (see Fig. 3 and supplementary Video S3). Such immoralists are often called “sanctimonious” or blamed for “double moral standards”, as they defect themselves, while enforcing the cooperation of others (for the purpose of exploitation). This is actually the main obstacle for the spreading of immoralists, as they have to pay punishment costs, while suffering from punishment fines as well. Therefore, immoralists need small punishment costs to survive. As cooperators die out quickly for moderate values of , the survival of immoralists depends on the existence of moralists they can exploit, otherwise they cannot outperform defectors. Conversely, moralists benefit from immoralists by supporting the punishment of defectors. Note, however, that this mutually profitable interaction between moralists and immoralists, which appears like an “unholy collaboration”, is fragile: If is increased, immoralists suffer from fines, and if is increased, punishing becomes too costly. In both cases, immoralists die out, and the coexistence of moralists and immoralists breaks down. Despite this fragility, “hypocritical” defectors, who punish other defectors, are known to occur in reality. Their existence has even been found in experiments [34], [35]. Here, we have revealed conditions for their occurrence.

thumbnail
Figure 3. Coexistence of moralists and immoralists for , , and , supporting the occurrence of individuals with ‘double moral standards’ (who punish defectors, while defecting themselves).

(a) Initially, at time , cooperators (blue), defectors (red), moralists (green) and immoralists (yellow) are uniformly distributed over the spatial lattice. (b) After 250 iterations, cooperators have been eliminated in the competition with defectors (as the synergy effect of cooperation is not large enough), and defectors are prevailing. (c–e) The snapshots at , , and show the interdependence of moralists and immoralists, which appears like a tacit collaboration. It is visible that the two punishing strategies win the struggle with defectors by staying together. On the one hand, due to the additional punishment cost, immoralists can survive the competition with defectors only by exploiting moralists. On the other hand, immoralists support moralists in fighting defectors. (f) After 12000 iterations, defectors have disappeared completely, leading to a coexistence of clusters of moralists with immoralists.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000758.g003

Discussion

In summary, the second-order free-rider problem finds a natural and simple explanation, without requiring additional assumptions, if the local nature of most social interactions is taken into account and punishment efforts are large enough. In fact, the presence of spatial interactions can change the system behavior so dramatically that we do not find the dominance of free-riders (defectors) as in the case of well-mixed interactions, but a prevalence of moralists via a “who laughs last laughs best” effect (Fig. 2). Moralists can escape disadvantageous kinds of competition with cooperators by spatial segregation. However, their triumph over all the other strategies requires the temporary presence of defectors, who diminish the cooperators (second-order free-riders). Finally, moralists can take over, as they have reached a superiority over cooperators (which is further growing) and as they can outcompete defectors (conventional free-riders).

Our findings stress how crucial spatial or network interactions in social systems are. Their consideration gives rise to a rich variety of possible dynamics and a number of continuous or discontinuous transitions between qualitatively different system behaviors. Spatial interactions can even invert the finally expected system behavior and, thereby, explain a number of challenging puzzles of social, economic, and biological systems. This includes the higher-than-expected level of cooperation in social dilemma situations, the elimination of second-order free-riders, and the formation of what looks like a collaboration between otherwise inferior strategies.

By carefully scanning the parameter space, we found several possible kinds of coexistence between two strategies each:

  • Moralists (M) and defectors (D) can coexist, when the disadvantage of cooperative behavior is not too large (i.e. the synergy factor is high enough), and if the punishment fine is sufficiently large that moralists can survive among defectors, but not large enough to get rid of them.
  • Instead of M and D, moralists (M) and immoralists (I) coexist, when the punishment cost is small enough. The small punishment cost is needed to ensure that the disadvantage of punishing defectors (I) compared to non-punishing defectors (D) is small enough that it can be compensated by the additional punishment efforts contributed by moralists.
  • To explain the well-known coexistence of D and C [11], it is useful to remember that defectors can be crowded out by cooperators, when the synergy factor exceeds a critical value (even when punishment is not considered). Slightly below this threshold, neither cooperators nor defectors have a sufficient advantage to get rid of the other strategy, which results in a coexistence of both strategies.

Generally, a coexistence of strategies occurs, when the payoffs at the interface between clusters of different strategies are balanced. In order to understand why the coexistence is possible in a certain parameter area rather than just for an infinitely small parameter set, it is important to consider that typical cluster sizes vary with the parameter values. This also changes the typical radius of the interface between the coexisting strategies and, thereby, the typical number of neighbors applying the same strategy or a different one. In other words, a change in the shape of a cluster can partly counter-balance payoff differences between two strategies by varying the number of “friends” and “enemies” involved in the battle at the interface between spatial areas with different strategies (see Fig. 4).

thumbnail
Figure 4. Dependence of cluster shapes on the punishment fine in the stationary state, supporting an adaptive balance between the payoffs of two different strategies at the interface between competing clusters.

Snapshots in the top row were obtained for low punishment fines, while the bottom row depicts results obtained for higher values of . (a) Coexistence of moralists and defectors for a synergy factor , punishment cost , and punishment fine . (b) Same parameters, apart from . (c) Coexistence of moralists and immoralists for , , and . (d) Same parameters, apart from . A similar change in the cluster shapes is found for the coexistence of cooperators and defectors, if the synergy factor is varied.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000758.g004

Finally, we would like to discuss the robustness of our observations. It is well-known that the level of cooperation in the public goods game is highest in small groups [10]. However, we have found that moralists can crowd out non-punishing cooperators also for group sizes of , 13, 21, or 25 interacting individuals, for example. In the limiting case of large groups, where everybody interacts with everybody else, we expect the outcome of the well-mixed case, which corresponds to defection by everybody (if other mechanisms like reputation effects [11] or abstaining are not considered [20]). That is, the same mechanisms that can create cooperation among friends may fail to establish shared moral standards, when spatial interactions are negligible. It would therefore be interesting to study, whether the fact that interactions in the financial system are global, has contributed to the financial crisis. Typically, when social communities exceed a certain size, they need sanctioning institutions to stabilize cooperation (such as laws, an executive system, and police).

Note that our principal discoveries are not expected to change substantially for spatial interactions within irregular grids (i.e. neighborhoods different from Moore neighborhoods) [47]. In case of network interactions, we have checked that small-world or random networks lead to similar results, when the degree distribution is the same (see Fig. 5). A heterogeneous degree distribution is even expected to reduce free-riding [37] (given the average degree is the same). Finally, adding other cooperation-promoting mechanisms to our model such as direct reciprocity (a shadow of the future through repeated interactions [48]), indirect reciprocity [17] (trust and reputation effects [11], [18]), abstaining from a joint enterprize [19][23], or success-driven migration [49], will strengthen the victory of moralists over conventional and second-order free-riders.

thumbnail
Figure 5. Resulting fractions of the four strategies C, D, I, and M, for random regular graphs as a function of the punishment fine .

The graphs were constructed by rewiring links of a square lattice of size with probability , thereby preserving the degree distribution (i.e. every player has 4 nearest neighbors) [59]. For small values of , small-world properties result, while for , we have a random regular graph. By keeping the degree distribution fixed, we can study the impact of randomness in the network structure independently of other effects. An inhomogeneous degree distribution can further promote cooperation [37]. The results displayed here are averages over 10 simulation runs for the model parameters , , and . Similar results can be obtained also for other parameter combinations.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000758.g005

In order to test the robustness of our observations, we have also checked the effect of randomness (“noise”) originating from the possibility of strategy mutations. It is known that mutations may promote cooperation [50]. According to the numerical analysis of the spatial public goods game with punishment, the introduction of rare mutations does not significantly change the final outcome of the competition between moralists and non-punishing cooperators. Second-order free-riders will always be a negligible minority in the end, if the fine-to-cost ratio and mutation rate allows moralists to spread. While a large mutation rate naturally causes a uniform distribution of strategies, a low level of strategy mutations can be even beneficial for moralists. Namely, by permanently generating a number of defectors, small mutation rates can considerably accelerate the spreading of moralists, i.e. the slow logarithmic coarsening is replaced by another kind of dynamics [51]. Defectors created by mutations play the same role as in the phase (see Figs. 1+2). They put moralists into an advantage over non-punishing cooperators, resulting in a faster spreading of the moralists (which facilitates the elimination of second-order free-riders over realistic time periods). In this way, the presence of a few “bad guys” (defectors) can accelerate the spreading of moral standards. Metaphorically speaking, we call this “lucifer's positive side effect”.

The current study paves the road for several interesting extensions. It is possible, for example, to study antisocial punishment [52], considering also strategies which punish cooperators [53]. The conditions for the survival or spreading of antisocial punishers can be identified by the same methodology, but the larger number of strategies creates new phases in the parameter space. While the added complexity transcends what can be discussed here, the current study demonstrates clearly how differentiated the moral dynamics in a society facing public goods problems can be and how it depends on a variety of factors (such as the punishment cost, punishment fine, and synergy factor). Going one step further, evolutionary game theory may even prove useful to understand how moral feelings have evolved.

Furthermore, it would be interesting to investigate the emergence of punishment within the framework of a coevolutionary model [54][56], where both, individual strategies and punishment levels are simultaneously spread. Such a model could, for example, assume that individuals show some exploration behavior [50] and stick to successful punishment levels for a long time, while they quickly abandon unsuccessful ones. In the beginning of this coevolutionary process, costly punishment would not pay off. However, after a sufficiently long time, mutually fitting punishment strategies are expected to appear in the same neighborhood by coincidence [49]. Once an over-critical number of successful punishment strategies have appeared in some area of the simulated space, they are eventually expected to spread. The consideration of success-driven migration should strongly support this process [49]. Over many generations, genetic-cultural coevolution could finally inherit costly punishment as a behavioral trait, as is suggested by the mechanisms of strong reciprocity [57].

Methods

We study the public goods game with punishment. Cooperative individuals (C and M) make a contribution of 1 to the public good, while defecting individuals (D and I) contribute nothing. The sum of all contributions is multiplied by and the resulting amount equally split among the interacting individuals. A defecting individual (D or I) suffers a fine by each punisher among the interaction partners, and each punishment requires a punisher (M or I) to spend a cost on each defecting individual among the interaction partners. In other words, only defectors and punishing defectors (immoralists) are punished, and the overall punishment is proportional to the sum of moralists and immoralists among the neighbors. The scaling by serves to make our results comparable with models studying different groups sizes.

Denoting the number of so defined cooperators, defectors, moralists, and immoralists among the interaction partners by , , and , respectively, an individual obtains the following payoff: If it is a cooperator, it gets , if a defector, the payoff is , a moralist receives , and an immoralist obtains . Our model of the spatial variant of this game studies interactions in a simple social network allowing for clustering. It assumes that individuals are distributed on a square lattice with periodic boundary conditions and play a public goods game with neighbors. We work with a fully occupied lattice of size with in Fig. 1 and in Figs. 24 (the lattice size must be large enough to avoid an accidental extinction of a strategy). The initial strategies of the individuals are equally and uniformly distributed. Then, we perform a random sequential update. The individual at the randomly chosen location belongs to five groups. (It is the focal individual of a Moore neighborhood and a member of the Moore neighborhoods of four nearest neighbors). It plays the public goods game with the interaction partners of a group , and obtains a payoff in all 5 groups it belongs to. The overall payoff is . Next, one of the four nearest neighbors is randomly chosen. Its location shall be denoted by and its overall payoff by . This neighbor imitates the strategy of the individual at location with probability [45]. That is, individuals tend to imitate better performing strategies in their neighborhood, but sometimes deviate (due to trial-and-error behavior or mistakes) [31]. Realistic noise levels lie between the two extremes (corresponding to unconditional imitation by the neighbor, whenever the overall payoff is higher than ) and (where the strategy is copied with probability 1/2, independently of the payoffs). For the noise level chosen in our study, the evolutionary selection pressure is high enough to eventually eliminate poorly performing strategies in favor of strategies with a higher overall payoff. This implies that the resulting frequency distribution of strategies in a large enough lattice is independent of the specific initial condition after a sufficiently long transient time. Close to the separating line between M and D+M in Fig. 1, the equilibration may require up to iterations (involving updates each).

Supporting Information

Video S1.

Indirect territorial battle between cooperators (blue) and moralists (green) in the presence of defectors (red). The computer simulation of the public goods game with punishment is performed for a grid of size LxL = 100×100, where the synergy factor of cooperation is r = 4.4, the punishment fine β = 0.1, and the punishment cost is γ = 0.1. For a detailed discussion of the spatiotemporal dynamics see the main text, particularly Fig. 2.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000758.s001

(4.26 MB AVI)

Video S2.

Temporal evolution of the coexistence between defectors (red) and cooperators (blue) for the parameter values r = 4.4, β = 0.1, and γ = 0.3.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000758.s002

(4.90 MB AVI)

Video S3.

Coexistence of moralists (green) and immoralists (yellow), who jointly defeat defectors (red). The computer simulation is performed for a grid of size LxL = 100×100, where the synergy factor of cooperation is r = 3.5, the punishment fine is β = 0.12, and the punishment cost is γ = 0.005. For a detailed discussion of the spatiotemporal dynamics see the main text, particularly Fig. 3.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000758.s003

(9.99 MB AVI)

Acknowledgments

D.H. would like to thank for useful comments by Carlos P. Roca, Moez Draief, Stefano Balietti, Thomas Chadefaux, and Sergi Lozano.

Author Contributions

Conceived and designed the experiments: DH AS MP GS. Performed the experiments: DH AS MP GS. Wrote the paper: DH AS MP GS.

References

  1. 1. Hardin G (1968) The tragedy of the commons. Science 162: 1243–1248.
  2. 2. Fehr E, Gächter S (2002) Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature 415: 137–140.
  3. 3. Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2003) The nature of human altruism. Nature 425: 785–791.
  4. 4. Hammerstein P, editor. (2003) Genetic and Cultural Evolution of Cooperation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  5. 5. Nakamaru M, Iwasa Y (2006) The evolution of altruism and punishment: Role of selfish punisher. J Theor Biol 240: 475–488.
  6. 6. Camerer CF, Fehr E (2006) When does “economic man” dominate social behavior. Science 311: 47–52.
  7. 7. Gurerk O, Irlenbusch B, Rockenbach B (2006) The competitive advantage of sanctioning institutions. Science 312: 108–111.
  8. 8. Sigmund K, Hauert C, Nowak MA (2001) Reward and punishment. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 98: 10757–10762.
  9. 9. Henrich J, Boyd R (2001) Why people punish defectors. J Theor Biol 208: 79–89.
  10. 10. Boyd R, Gintis H, Bowles S, Richerson PJ (2003) The evolution of altruistic punishment. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 100: 3531–3535.
  11. 11. Brandt H, Hauert C, Sigmund K (2003) Punishing and reputation in spatial public goods games. Proc R Soc Lond Ser B 270: 1099–1104.
  12. 12. Yamagishi T (1986) The provision of a sanctioning system as a public good. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 51: 110–116.
  13. 13. Fehr E (2004) Don't lose your reputation. Nature 432: 449–450.
  14. 14. Colman AM (2006) The puzzle of cooperation. Nature 440: 744–745.
  15. 15. Fowler JH (2005) Second-order free-riding problem solved? Nature 437: E8–E8.
  16. 16. Panchanathan K, Boyd R (2005) Reply. Nature 437: E8–E9.
  17. 17. Panchanathan K, Boyd R (2004) Indirect reciprocity can stabilize cooperation without the second-order free rider problem. Nature 432: 499–502.
  18. 18. Milinski M, Semmann D, Krambeck H-J (2002) Reputation helps to solve the “tragedy of the commons”. Nature 415: 424–426.
  19. 19. Fowler JH (2005) Altruistic punishment and the origin of cooperation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 102: 7047–7049.
  20. 20. Brandt H, Hauert C, Sigmund K (2006) Punishing and abstaining for public goods. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 103: 495–497.
  21. 21. Hauert C, Traulsen A, Brandt H, Nowak MA, Sigmund K (2007) Via freedom to coercion: The emergence of costly punishment. Science 316: 1905–1907.
  22. 22. Hauert C, De Monte S, Hofbauer J, Sigmund K (2002) Volunteering as red queen mechanism for cooperation in public goods game. Science 296: 1129–1132.
  23. 23. Semmann D, Krambeck H-J, Milinski M (2003) Volunteering leads to rock-paper-scissors dynamics in a public goods game. Nature 425: 390–393.
  24. 24. Milinski M, Sommerfeld RD, Krambeck HJ, Reed FA, Marotzke J (2008) The collective-risk social dilemma and the prevention of simulated dangerous climate change. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 105: 2291–2294.
  25. 25. Sigmund K (2010) The Calculus of Selfishness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  26. 26. Heckathorn DD (1996) The dynamics and dilemmas of collective action. American Sociological Review 61: 250–277.
  27. 27. Eldakar OT, Wilson DS (2008) Selfishness as second-order altruism. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 109: 6982–6986.
  28. 28. Nakamaru M, Iwasa Y (2005) The evolution of altruism by costly punishment in the lattice structured population: Score-dependent viability versus score-dependent fertility. Evolutionary Ecology Research 7: 853–870.
  29. 29. Sekiguchi T, Nakamaru M (2009) Effect of the presence of empty sites on the evolution of cooperation by costly punishment in spatial games. Journal of Theoretical Biology 256(2): 297–304.
  30. 30. Nowak MA (2006) Five rules for the evolution of cooperation. Science 314: 1560–1563.
  31. 31. Traulsen A, et al. (2010) Human strategy updating in evolutionary games. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 107: 2962–2966.
  32. 32. Nowak MA, Tarnita CE, Antal T (2010) Evolutionary dynamics in structured populations. Phil Trans R Soc B 365: 19–30.
  33. 33. Hauser MD (2006) Moral Minds: How Nature Designed Our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong. New York: Ecco.
  34. 34. Falk A, Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2005) Driving forces behind informal sanctions. Econometrica 73: 2017–2030.
  35. 35. Shinada M, Yamagishi T, Ohmura Y (2004) False friends are worse than bitter enemies: “Altruistic” punishment of in-group members. Evol Hum Behav 25: 379–393.
  36. 36. Szabó G, Hauert C (2002) Phase transitions and volunteering in spatial public goods games. Phys Rev Lett 89: 118101.
  37. 37. Santos FC, Santos MD, Pacheco JM (2008) Social diversity promotes the emergence of cooperation in public goods games. Nature 454: 213–216.
  38. 38. Wakano JY, Nowak MA, Hauert C (2009) Spatial dynamics of ecological public goods. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 106: 7910–7914.
  39. 39. Nowak MA, May RM (1992) Evolutionary games and spatial chaos. Nature 359: 826–829.
  40. 40. Nowak MA, Bonhoeffer S, May RM (1994) More spatial games. Int J Bifurcat Chaos 4: 33–56.
  41. 41. Nowak MA, Bonhoeffer S, May RM (1994) Spatial games and the maintenance of cooperation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 91: 4877–4881.
  42. 42. Nowak MA, Bonhoeffer S, May RM (1996) Robustness of cooperation. Nature 379: 125–126.
  43. 43. Nathanson CG, Tarnita CE, Nowak MA (2009) Calculating evolutionary dynamics in structured populations. PLoS Comput Biol 5: e1000615.
  44. 44. Pacheco JM, Pinheiro FL, Santos FC (2009) Population structure induces a symmetry breaking favoring the emergence of cooperation. PLoS Comput Biol 5: e1000596.
  45. 45. Szabó G, Töke C (1998) Evolutionary prisoner's dilemma game on a square lattice. Phys Rev E 58: 69–73.
  46. 46. Dornic I, Chaté H, Chave J, Hinrichsen H (2001) Critical coarsening without surface tension: The universality class of the voter model. Phys Rev Lett 87: 045701.
  47. 47. Flache A, Hegselmann R (2001) Do irregular grids make a difference? Relaxing the spatial regularity assumption in cellular models of social dynamics. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 4: 4. see http://www.soc.surrey.ac.uk/JASSS/4/4/6.html.
  48. 48. Axelrod R (1984) The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.
  49. 49. Helbing D, Yu W (2009) The outbreak of cooperation among success-driven individuals under noisy conditions. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 106: 3680–3685.
  50. 50. Traulsen A, Hauert C, Silva HD, Nowak MA, Sigmund K (2009) Exploration dynamics in evolutionary games. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 106: 709–712.
  51. 51. Helbing D, Szolnoki A, Perc M, Szabó G (2010) Defector-accelerated cooperativeness in public goods games with punishment and mutations, in preparation.
  52. 52. Herrmann B, Thöni C, Gächter S (2008) Antisocial punishment across societies. Science 319: 1362–1367.
  53. 53. Rand DG, Ohtsuki H, Nowak MA (2009) Direct reciprocity with costly punishment: Generous tit-for-tag prevails. J Theor Biol 256: 45–57.
  54. 54. Szabó G, Szolnoki A, Jeromos V (2009) Selection of dynamical rules in spatial Prisoner's Dilemma games. EPL 87: 18007.
  55. 55. Santos FC, Pacheco JM, Lenaerts T (2006) Cooperation prevails when individuals adjust their social ties. PLoS Comput Biol 2: 1284–1291.
  56. 56. Perc M, Szolnoki A (2010) Coevolutionary games - A mini review. BioSystems 99: 109–125.
  57. 57. Bowles S, Gintis H (2004) The evolution of strong reciprocity: Cooperation in heterogeneous populations. Theor Popul Biol 65: 17–28.
  58. 58. Helbing D, Szolnoki A, Perc M, Szabó G (2010) Spreading of costly punishment and evolutionary resonance in the spatial public goods game, in preparation.
  59. 59. Szabó G, Szolnoki A, Izsák R (2004) Rock-scissors-paper game on regular small-world networks. J Phys A: Math Gen 37: 2599–2609.